Footnote to the 2003 Reith Lectures


Professor V. S. Ramachandran's wonderful Reith Lectures -- like his equally wonderful book Phantoms in the Brain, co-authored with Sandra Blakeslee -- gave many telling examples, from clinical and experimental neuroscience including phantom-limb pain relief, showing how the brain functions as a `committee' of multifarious parts. Then, in the final lecture broadcast on 30 April 2003, Ramachandran returned to the problem of why, despite that multifariousness, every normal human being seems to have a strong sense of his or her unique `self' -- an entity, as he put it, that

  1. has continuity in time,
  2. has unity and coherence (not a committee but a single entity),
  3. is (a) embodied, and (b), I would add, well-oriented in its surroundings (e.g., we are normally clear whether we are inside a room or on a mountaintop) and
  4. is an agent with free will.

(These days, one might add "has a sense of gender distinct from biological or chromosomal sex, even though the two often coincide.) Ramachandran then pointed out that these properties of `self' are amenable to experimental investigation. Thus for instance property 3a, embodiment, can be switched off by stimulating a certain spot in the right parietal cortex, producing a classic `out of the body' experience.

He then mentioned different approaches to explaining these properties, and suggested that all we might need is an Einsteinian shift in perspective, in order to see a relatively simple answer `staring at us all along'.

Well, I would never dream of comparing myself to Einstein, but I did see what plainly seemed to be the required shift in perspective, some years ago. It was simple and it was staring at me, and I published it in 1997 in a little-known paper entitled Lucidity and Science, Part II: From acausality illusions and free will to final theories, mathematics, and music. I've discussed it further in my recent book Science, Music, and Mathematics: The Deepest Connections. The key idea is hardly new -- going back at least to Kant, with adumbrations in Plato -- but its explanatory power still seems to me to be vastly underestimated. It strongly illuminates the classic issues about self, consciousness, and free will, and the more technical issues about such things as phantom-limb pain relief, cross-modal perception (e.g. McGurk lip-reading effect) and our sense of time -- issues that are often thought mysterious. The shift in perspective comes simply from taking seriously the idea that perception works by model-fitting. The brain actively fits internal models to data from the outside world, as Gunnar Johansson's `walking lights' demonstration (courtesy James B. Maas) clearly suggests:

Gunnar Johansson's `walking lights' demo, courtesy James Maas

(Everyone with normal vision sees a person walking. This perceptual phenomenon is very robust; it is an easily repeatable experiment. Vision researchers discuss it under headings such as `structure from motion'. Active model-fitting, unconscious of course, seems to me to be the only way to make sense of how a mere twelve moving dots in two dimensions, twelve dots moving on your retina, give rise to the percept of a nontrivial three-dimensional structure. Quite specific unconscious assumptions are involved, such as piecewise rigidity. defining the internal geometrical model that mediates your percept of a person walking. A model, however encoded, is a partial and approximate representation of reality -- an entity fundamental to how perception works and, incidentally, fundamental to how science works too.)

How, then, does all this bear on the problem of self? Here's a quick version of my answer, as published in Lucidity and Science, Part II (page 292). It's close to the answer suggested by Professor Ramachandran, but not quite the same because I would argue that we're talking about something that's evolutionarily far more ancient -- something we share with leopards and their prey and indeed all animals with brains:

However diverse our internal makeup may be, in order to survive we need, continually, to make sense of our surroundings and our own location and orientation in those surroundings. So the repertoire of internal models and sub-models that are used to construct the perceived world, with its stationary and moving objects, has to include a self-model. Simultaneously with other models, this has to be fitted to the incoming sensory data including, now, internal data from one's own body, such as proprioceptive data about limb positions. The end result is a single spatiotemporal model of oneself in one's surroundings. If this model-fitting process fails, one may become `disoriented'...

From this viewpoint, properties (1)-(3) above are just what one would expect, in consequence of the properties the internal models must have if they are to promote survival, e.g., coherence, self-consistency, and continuity in time. I try to discuss these issues very carefully in the Lucidity and Science papers and in my recent book.

I also discuss (4), the ancient issue of free will. Here you need a little more than just the one paragraph. The relevant, larger chunk of Lucidity and Science Part II, containing the above paragraph, is reproduced below with literature references omitted.

Before presenting the chunk a preliminary point needs to be made, about our subjective sense of time. Just as there are perceptual illusions about spatial relations -- an inevitable aspect of the internal model-fitting process -- there are `acausality illusions' about temporal relations. Effects may seem to precede causes, usually by a modest fraction of a second. The experimental phenomena are clearcut and easily verifiable. There is no mystery if you recognize that `time', as perceived subjectively, must be a property of an internal model. It is therefore not the same thing as physical time, and it therefore need not respect causality in the usual sense of physics.

Music is `the art that is made out of time', as the great novelist Ursula le Guin once put it; and the existence of acausality illusions becomes especially clear to anyone who looks closely at how music works. This too is discussed in Lucidity and Science, Part II and in my book. For instance, perceived harmony changes can precede the arrival of the acoustic data defining them. I give a simple example from Mozart.

Recently much discussed is the slowing-down of perceived time experienced by people who get into a gunfight, or who survive falling from a roof, or who are one of Professor David Eagleman's SCAD divers. Again there is nothing mysterious if we remember that perceived time is an internal model property. The perception that things happen `in slow motion' must come from interrogating an internal model already formed, and so like anything else we perceive is always -- can only be -- something within short-term or longer-term memory.

Here is the chunk from Lucidity and Science, Part II (pages 292-293), following the discussion of acausality illusions and addressing the implications for the free-will problem, Ramachandran's point (4):

2.7 Consciousness and free will   (see also the Footnote on free will below)

The biological need to grasp space and time together includes the need to coordinate internal decisions with external events. So, again not surprisingly, there is a second kind of acausality illusion, which concerns the perceived time of taking a decision to act. This point has been overlooked in some of the debates about consciousness and free will.

Perhaps the most striking example, with the clearest experimental evidence, is the acausality illusion evoked in the slide-projector experiment of Grey Walter. This was first described in 1963 in an unpublished report. Neurosurgical patients were invited to entertain themselves to a slide show by pressing a button to advance the slide projector, at times of their choosing. But the projector was wired not to the button but directly to a certain part of the patient's motor cortex; and the subjective effect -- startling and disconcerting to the patients, who must have wondered whether they were going crazy -- was that the projector seemed to behave acausally, to anticipate their decisions. The projector seemed to advance itself just before they decided or, rather, perceived themselves as deciding, to press the button.

[Professor Ramachandran described examples of essentially similar phenomena; you can find these in the transcript of Lecture 5 under the phrase Readiness Potential.]

This too is easily accommodated by the model-fitting hypothesis, which says that perceived times, including perceived times of taking decisions, and perceived times of pressing buttons, are properties of the brain's internal models rather than the physical times of any associated cortical activity. It also underlines the point about free will. The existence of acausality illusions implies that questions about the perceived times of decisions are entirely separate from questions about whether the decisions were taken freely or not. There was no reason, in this experiment, to doubt the patients' freedom to decide to press the button, where freedom is understood in the ordinary, everyday sense related to personal responsibility. The experiments add to our knowledge about perceived times and acausality illusions, but say nothing at all about personal freedom of choice, and personal reponsibility for our actions. They do not say, in other words, that free will is illusory. What is illusory is the perceived time of willing the action.

In principle, the experiment could be repeated with a gun instead of a slide projector. The point is that questions about whether the patient intended to murder someone are separate from -- are nothing to do with -- questions about the precise timing of the murder, about whether the bullet struck the victim a fraction of a second earlier than intended.

The model-fitting hypothesis says that the conscious self, the perceived self that I experience as having intentionality, as being free to make choices, as planning things and taking decisions, must, like any other percept, arise from an internal model: the single internal model that my brain fits to my real, biologically diverse, multi-component, multifariously subtle self. As Jack Cohen and Ian Stewart have aptly put it, the brain viewed from outside looks more like a committee, composed of different parts that evolved at different times for different purposes, echoed in common experience: `something tells me that....', `my head says one thing but my heart another', and so on. Yet `I am utterly convinced that there is only one me... not some kind of committee.' The model-fitting hypothesis makes sense of this paradox: the brain has multifarious parts, but only one self-model.

However diverse our internal makeup may be, in order to survive we need, continually, to make sense of our surroundings and our own location and orientation in those surroundings. So the repertoire of internal models and sub-models that are used to construct the perceived world, with its stationary and moving objects, has to include a self-model. Simultaneously with other models, this has to be fitted to the incoming sensory data including, now, internal data from one's own body, such as proprioceptive data about limb positions. The end result is a single spatiotemporal model of oneself in one's surroundings. If this model-fitting process fails, one may become `disoriented'. Because of the need to coordinate internal decisions with external events in fast-moving situations, the model property called perceived time must be a single property, defined consistently, of the entire model of oneself in one's surroundings. It is this single model property that represents not only the `when' of when a ball is hit, or a piano key struck, but also the `when' of taking decisions or initiating action. Because cortical processing is necessary to arrive at even a snap decision, the perceived `when' of such a decision must, inevitably, be preceded by cortical activity, such as that causing Grey Walter's slide projector to advance.

In summary, then, the model-fitting hypothesis predicts that perceived times of internal decisions must be later than, and perceived times of outside-world events earlier than, at least some of the associated physical events in the nervous system. Only thus can the brain, with its finite rate of information processing, typically taking hundreds of milliseconds, consistently represent both sets of times in its internal model of the self in its surroundings at the far finer, millisecond, accuracies needed for survival. Free will and intentionality are properties of the self-model.


Footnote on free will: At the 2013 Hay-on-Wye Festival, where I gave a talk on some of the above, consultant psychiatrist Mark Salter provoked us with 'Free will is a biologically indispensable illusion.'  I liked this rather neat statement, but wanted to add a second statement, that free will and the sense of self are socially indispensable realities.

There is no conflict between the two statements, because they belong to different levels of description. Among the many interesting contributions at the Festival I was also struck by some from my cosmologist colleague George F. R. Ellis, famous in scientific circles for his classic work with Stephen Hawking. George underlined the point that to make sense of our surroundings it's essential to recognize many levels of description -- reflecting the many hierarchical layers of complexity in the real world, and their `emergent properties'. That point is also well made, I think, in the abovementioned Cohen and Stewart work (The Collapse of Chaos, Penguin 1994) and, more recently and even more cogently, in a molecular-biological context, by the physiologist Denis Noble (The Music of Life: Biology Beyond Genes, Oxford 2006).

An incessant cause of philosophical confusion is the ambiguity lurking within the words `reality' and `illusion', when applied to perceptual experiences. Again it's because of the way perception works, namely by model-fitting. So there's no clearcut or absolute dichotomy between `reality' and `illusion'. It's yet another of our false dichotomies. More apt is to say that some of the brain's internal models fit outside-world reality more accurately than others.


Footnote on eternal life: One of many questions beyond the scope of science is what happens to subjective time at death. Notwithstanding the prodigious assurance with which some scientists assert the impossibility of eternal life after death, no-one can say whether subjective time does or does not stretch to infinity. Who knows, repentance on your deathbed might be a better idea than some people think.


Footnote on neuroscience: A recent review shows hints of the brain's active model-fitting processes, identifying `top-down' as well as `bottom-up' neural pathways: C. D. Gilbert and Wu Li, 2013: Top-down influences on visual processing. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 14, 350-363. George Ellis kindly drew my attention to it.


Here again is the link to the published papers, Lucidity and Science, etc (http://www.damtp.cam.ac.uk/user/mem/papers/LHCE/)
This page is at http://www.damtp.cam.ac.uk/user/mem/reith.html
Back to my home page, http://www.damtp.cam.ac.uk/user/mem/
Back to the preview of my recent book.
Michael Edgeworth McIntyre (M.E.McIntyre at-sign damtp.cam.ac.uk), postal address 98 Windsor Road, Cambridge CB4 3JN, UK.

Copyright © Michael Edgeworth McIntyre 2003. Last updated 29 Sept 2023
Valid HTML 4.01!